The Poverty of Analysis

@article{Papineau2009ThePO,
  title={The Poverty of Analysis},
  author={David Papineau},
  journal={Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume},
  year={2009},
  volume={83},
  pages={1-30}
}
  • D. Papineau
  • Published 2009
  • Philosophy
  • Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume
I argue that philosophy is like science in three interesting and non-obvious ways. First, the claims made by philosophy are synthetic, not analytic: philosophical claims, just like scientific claims, are not guaranteed by the structure of the concepts they involve. Second, philosophical knowledge is a posteriori, not a priori: the claims established by philosophers depend on the same kind of empirical support as scientific theories. And finally, the central questions of philosophy concern… Expand
Down to earth philosophy: an anti-exceptionalist essay on thought experiments and philosophical methodology
In the first part of the dissertations, chapters 1 to 3, I criticize several views which tend to set philosophy apart from other cognitive achievements. I argue against the popular views that 1)Expand
Armchair philosophy naturalized
TLDR
It is argued that since many results of the sciences can be construed as stemming from conceptual engineering as well, Carnap's account of philosophy can be methodologically naturalistic and defended the relevance of the analytic–synthetic distinction against criticisms by Quine, Demopoulos, and Papineau. Expand
On a Straw Man in the Philosophy of Science: A Defense of the Received View
  • Sebastian Lutz
  • Philosophy
  • HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science
  • 2012
The Received View on scientific theories as developed by Carnap, Hempel, and Feigl is now generally considered to have failed for a variety of reasons, bringing down a number of dependentExpand
Artificial language philosophy of science
Artificial language philosophy (also called ‘ideal language philosophy’) is the position that philosophical problems are best solved or dissolved through a reform of language. Its underlyingExpand
THOUGHT EXPERIMENTS AND DISGUISED ARGUMENTS
One of the most controversial methods of philosophy is the use of thought experiments. If, on the one hand, philosophers usually agree that a hypothetical reasoning or an imaginative example canExpand
Phenomenology and the Scientific Image: Defending Naturalism from Its Critics
At the beginning of the twentieth century, why did Husserl think a new philosophical method was needed? Why phenomenology? For Husserl, what primarily motivated the development of a new philosophicalExpand
Critical Theory's Philosophy
Critical Theory has an uneasy relationship to philosophy, and it is a complex question whether it constitutes a philosophical position at all: it both aims to leave philosophy behind and insists onExpand
Naturalised modal epistemology and quasi-realism
Given quasi-realism, the claim is that any attempt to naturalise modal epistemology would leave out absolute necessity. The reason, according to Simon Blackburn, is that we cannot offer an empiricalExpand
Conceptual analysis without concepts
“Conceptual analysis” is a misnomer—it refers, but it does not refer to a method or practice that involves the analysis of concepts. Once this is recognized, many of the main arguments for skepticismExpand
TWO CONCEPTS OF RATIONALITY
RATIONALITY IS ESSENTIALLY connected with norms. In Western philosophy, while there has been much disagreement over what the norms of rationality are, there seems to have been substantial agreementExpand
...
1
2
3
4
5
...

References

SHOWING 1-10 OF 13 REFERENCES
PHILOSOPHICAL INTUITIONS: THEIR TARGET, THEIR SOURCE, AND THEIR EPISTEMIC STATUS
Summary Intuitions play a critical role in analytical philosophical activity. But do they qualify as genuine evidence for the sorts of conclusions philosophers seek? Skeptical arguments againstExpand
Thinking about Consciousness
Preface Introduction 1. The Case for Materialism 2. Conceptual Dualism 3. The Impossibility of Zombies 4. Phenomenal Concepts 5. The Explanatory Gap 6. The Intuition of Distinctness 7. Prospects forExpand
Metaethics and the empirical sciences
What contribution can the empirical sciences make to metaethics? This paper outlines an argument to a particular metaethical conclusion—that moral judgments are epistemically unjustified—that dependsExpand
Knowledge and Its Place in Nature
1. Investigating Knowledge Itself 2. Knowledge as a Natural Phenomenon 3. Human Knowledge and Social Practices 4. Human Knowledge and Reflection 5. Normativity and Natural Knowledge 6. WhatExpand
Making it Explicit Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University
  • 1994
KRIPKE'S PROOF IS AD HOMINEM NOT TWO-DIMENSIONAL
Kripke’s Argument is Ad Hominem Not Two-Dimensional
Modal Epistemology and the Rationalist Renaissance
Reason, Expression, and the Philosophical Enterprise
  • 2001
...
1
2
...