Condorcet's paradox and anonymous preference profiles

@article{Gehrlein1976CondorcetsPA,
  title={Condorcet's paradox and anonymous preference profiles},
  author={William V. Gehrlein and Peter C. Fishburn},
  journal={Public Choice},
  year={1976},
  volume={26},
  pages={1-18}
}
Condorcet's paradox [6] of simple majority voting occurs in a voting situation with n voters and m candidates or alternatives if for every alternative there is a second alternative which more voters prefer to the first alternative than conversely. The paradox can arise only if the strict simple majority relation on the alternatives is cyclic, provided that m is finite. Studies of the paradox are usually based either on profiles or A-profiles (anonymous preference profiles). A profile is a… Expand
Condorcet's paradox and the likelihood of its occurrence: different perspectives on balanced preferences*
Many studies have considered the probability that a pairwise majority rule (PMR) winner exists for three candidate elections. The absence of a PMR winner indicates an occurrence of Condorcet'sExpand
Uniform generation of anonymous and neutral preference profiles for social choice rules
TLDR
An exact formula for the number of equivalence classes of preference profiles (called roots) in the Impartial Anonymous and Neutral Culture model of social choice is derived, and a symbolic algebra routine that can be used for Monte-Carlo algorithms for the study of various structural properties of SCRs is described. Expand
Multi-Winner Scoring Election Methods: Condorcet Consistency and Paradoxes
TLDR
A comparison of four multi-winner voting rules, k-Plurality, k -Negative Plurality), k-Borda, and Bloc, which can be considered as generalisations of well-known single-winner scoring rules, based on the likelihood of two paradoxes of committee elections. Expand
The Chairman’s Paradox Revisited
TLDR
This paper re-examines the so-called ‘chairman’s paradox’ and replaces the standard assumption of linear preference orders with weak preference orders, which allow for indifference, and points to a new paradox of sophisticated voting. Expand
A Note on the Likelihood of the Absolute Majority Paradoxes
For three-candidate elections, we compute under the Impartial Anonymous Culture assumption, the conditional probabilities of the Absolute Majority Winner Paradox (AMWP) and the Absolute MajorityExpand
On the (Sample) Condorcet Efficiency of Majority Rule: An alternative view of majority cycles and social homogeneity
The Condorcet efficiency of a social choice procedure is usually defined as the probability that this procedure coincides with the majority winner (or majority ordering) in random samples, given aExpand
Multi-winner scoring election methods: Condorcet consistency and paradoxes
The goal of this paper is to propose a comparison of four multi-winner voting rules, k-Plurality, k-Negative Plurality, k-Borda, and Bloc. These four election methods are extensions of usual scoringExpand
Coincidence probabilities for simple majority and positional voting rules
Abstract With three candidates and an odd number n of voters, let Q ( n , λ , p ) be the probability that the winning candidate under the point-total rule that assigns 1, λ, and 0 points respectivelyExpand
The impact of dependence among voters’ preferences with partial indifference
Standard weighted scoring rules do not directly accommodate the possibility that some voters might have dichotomous preferences in three-candidate elections. The direct solution to this issue wouldExpand
Constant scoring rules for choosing one among many alternatives
ConclusionsWhen a group is to select a decision alternative from a finite set of m ⩾ 3 feasible alternatives, it is often desirable to choose the Condorect (majority) alternative when there is one.Expand
...
1
2
3
4
5
...

References

SHOWING 1-10 OF 26 REFERENCES
Majority Decision-Making with Partial Unidimensionality*
A major dilemma for majority decision-making occurs when the summation of transitive individual preference orderings results in an intransitive social ordering. The problems posed by this phenomenon,Expand
The paradox of voting: probability calculations.
TLDR
It is shown that when all possible rankings of three alternatives are equally likely and the number of voters becomes very large, the probability of the paradox approaches a definite limit, vig .087. Expand
Some mathematical remarks on the paradox of voting
When a group of m individuals endeavours to choose a winner from a set of n alternatives by making all possible pairwise comparisons among the alternatives (using simple majority rule), there existsExpand
AGGREGATION OF PREFERENCES WITH VARIABLE ELECTORATE
IN THIS PAPER we consider procedures for going from several individual preferences among several alternatives, called candidates, to something which may be called a collective preference. TheExpand
A mathematical solution for the probability of the paradox of voting.
TLDR
Through the use of this model, a general solution for the probability of the paradox is derived, together with an approximation for computational convenience, and some numerical results are given. Expand
The Probability of a Cyclical Majority
Consider a committee or society attempting to order the alternatives (X_1, X_2, X_3) by use of majority rule. Each individual is assumed to have a strong ordering (called a profile) on theExpand
Social Choice and Individual Rankings II
This paper investigates social positional rules. The rules are social in that they produce a social output for any configuration of individual preference orderings. They are positional in that theExpand
Voter concordance, simple majorities, and group decision methods
This paper examines the effect of the degree of agreement among voters' preferences, as measured by the Kendall-Smith coefficient of concordance, on (1) the likelihood that one decision alternativeExpand
An analysis of simple two‐stage voting systems
TLDR
The propensities of alternative two-stage systems to elect the candidate which would be elected by a theoretically more sophisticated but less practical norm procedure such as simple majority of the Borda sum-of-ranks method are assessed. Expand
The theory of committees and elections
I The Theory of Committees and Elections.- I. A Committee and Motions.- II. Independent Valuation.- III. Can a Motion be Represented by the same Symbol on Different Schedules?.- IV. A Committee usingExpand
...
1
2
3
...